Monday, September 20, 2021

The errors of philosophers

We philosophers think of ourselves as mighty careful thinkers, and generally I think we are. But philosophers are prone to specific types of thinking errors. Hazards of the trade. Most anyone who tries to think philosophically will make them unless they learn not to. Here are a couple of related ones.

Mistaking the good for the true

Every philosopher knows the difference between is and ought. What is the case and what ought to be the case are two fundamentally different questions. But we are constantly tempted to conflate them.

To see what I am getting at, imagine someone tells you a disgusting joke. You might say, “That’s not funny, that’s cruel!” But humor doesn’t respect moral boundaries. Some really funny jokes are really offensive. Clearly, if you try to restrict the genuinely funny to jokes that give no offense, you will not advance much in your understanding of humor. But this is just the sort of mistake to which philosophers are prone.

For example, Plato inquired into the nature of reality and concluded that the physical world is not real. This is because the physical world is in a state of flux, and Plato disapproved of flux. On the basis of his moral preference for permanence he reasoned that reality must be a static world beyond all experience, of which our ever changing world is only a flickering shadow. Plato isn’t alone in succumbing to this sort of thinking. We all long for stability. Almost all major religions attempt to provide some promise of its existence on a different plane of being.

You might scoff: Plato didn’t just reason: “I disapprove of flux world, therefore there must be a stable one!” Right. He provided ingenious arguments for the reality of the Forms. But it is fundamentally motivated reasoning. Plato needed to approve of existence as much as he needed to understand it.

There is a basic pattern here which you should try to grasp: We identify an idea or concept that strikes us as both important and poorly grasped at an ordinary language level. Then we attempt to determine the real or genuine notion, using our moral intuitions as a guide. Let’s sketch a couple of other examples.

Free will

Everyone approves of free will, and most philosophers tend to develop theories that satisfy our estimation of it. Hume is a notable exception, and that is why Kant ridiculed Hume’s natural notion of free will as a “wretched subterfuge.” Hume suggested that we are free to whatever extent our actions are the outcome of our reasoned decisions. But this countenances the humiliating possibility that our reasoning processes are themselves fully determined. It is an inglorious notion, hence a false one.

Knowledge

Ordinary folks tend to think that knowledge is just something like useful information. Good stuff if you can get it. But philosophers esteem knowledge much more highly than this. The argument we like to bully students with is that you can acquire useful information by pure luck. You might, e.g., guess your roommate’s PIN and use it to make a withdrawal from her account. In this case, we insist you surely didn’t know the PIN. You merely guessed right.

This is a surprisingly persuasive argument. But if knowledge is a natural phenomenon, there is no reason to expect it to conform to our scruples. To this we should simply reply that guessed knowledge is no less knowledge than stumbled upon treasure is treasure. Guessing is just not a reliable way to achieve it.

Philosophical overreach

Of course, a lot of the concepts that philosophers study are moral in nature: justice, responsibility, liberty, rights, duties, etc. So you would think that in regard to such we surely do not err in developing theories that respect our moral intuitions. But indeed we do. We do this by trying to get a normative concept to do too much work. I will call this Philosophical Overreach.

In fact, philosophical overreach is what is happening in the above examples as well. We try to develop a concept that subsumes things that are conceptually distinct: nature and morality. The result is a morass that remains perpetually subject to counterexample. Within ethics proper, we do this by trying to pack too many different kinds of good (or bad) stuff into one concept. Here are a couple of examples:

The meaningful life

It is very easy to state what a meaningful life consists in. Life is meaningful to the extent that we care about the things we are involved in. The philosopher rejoins: That is not a genuinely meaningful life. What if you care about doing things that are evil? Hitler cared about what he was doing! But that just means that there is a difference between the meaningful life and the moral one. It is fine if we want to develop an overarching notion of the good life according to which it is meaningful, morally admirable and other good things as well. But these are different things and we achieve them in fundamentally different ways.

Moral obligation

This is Peter Singer’s notion of moral obligation: "If it is in our power to prevent something bad from happening, without thereby sacrificing anything of comparable moral importance, then we ought, morally, to do it". It doesn’t take long to discover that this is awesomely austere. e.g., It implies that morally you ought never to splurge on a fancy meal. You ought to eat simply and cheaply, and feed the hungry with the money you save.

Philosophers have many objections to this view, but one is that it can not be right because it entails that almost all people fail catastrophically to satisfy their basic moral obligations on a daily basis. They seek a less demanding theory that allows us to attach greater moral significance to our own happiness. But they are overreaching. Satisfying obligations is one good thing; satisfying our interests is another. To live well we must learn to balance, not conflate them.

G. Randolph Mayes
Department of Philosophy
Sacramento State

4 comments:

  1. Randy, "There is a basic pattern here which you should try to grasp: We identify an idea or concept that strikes us as both important and poorly grasped at an ordinary language level. Then we attempt to determine the real or genuine notion, using our moral intuitions as a guide."

    This is what Singer is doing, no?

    But I'll try to defend the objection to him you criticized: "it can not be right because it entails that almost all people fail catastrophically to satisfy their basic moral obligations on a daily basis."

    Unless morality is just something *out there*, we should think of it as a tremendous social and historical achievement, which allows us to live and cooperate with each other on more or less fair terms. Morality serves a set of profound social needs. It's crazy to think that these require something that entails that everyone catastrophically fails to satisfy on a daily basis. The problem isn't that we don't live up to Singer's principle; the problem is that his principle doesn't live up to us and what we need a morality for.

    ReplyDelete
  2. Hey Kyle,

    Regarding your first point, I'm not sure if he does it in the way that I find objectionable. I think it's necessary to use your moral intuitions as a guide to the clarification of moral concepts. The overreach I argue for in this area is trying to pack too much good stuff into it. I think you can make a similar point regarding Rawls' theory of justice, e.g.. I see Singer as spelling out the implications of a fundamentally utilitarian view. I do think utilitarianism carries some absurd consequences, but I am not confident saying they are the result of this kind of overreach.

    I accept your characterization of morality completely. I'm not sure I accept your defense of the criticism. Jesus set way too high a standard as well, but I don't think Christians draw the conclusion that Jesus failed us in prescribing his impossible message of love for ones fellow human.

    So if I were to defend Singer I would have him say: Look, I agree with you that morals are fundamentally norms that evolved to meet social cooperative aims, neither true nor false outside the domain of human intersubjectivity. But in the 21st century its clear that these norms have evolved to reflect a great deal of what we call utilitarianism, and I'm suggesting this is what a utilitarian notion of moral obligation looks like. Perhaps you are right that this analysis of moral obligation, if accepted universally, would undermine our cooperative goals, but that's surely not obvious. Human beings fall far short of all sorts of ideals, but that does not make us stop trying to do better in light of them.

    My main point is that if Singer's analysis is wrong, it is not because it fails to take full account of rational self-interest. In the same way, an analysis of the concept of rational self-interest won't be wrong for failing to take account of moral obligation.

    ReplyDelete
  3. Hi Randy. I'm inclined to agree with you about 'philosophical overreach' in general, but I'm not sold on some of your specifics.

    "[Plato] provided ingenious arguments for the reality of the Forms. But it is fundamentally motivated reasoning."

    First off I'm not sure how you could know this. Maybe you know Plato better than me and are thinking of clear points where he tips his hand? If so, I'd be curious what that passages those are.

    Second, the charge of motivated reasoning, by itself, seems ad hominem. Surely his arguments stand or fall on their own merits, regardless of his psychological motivations in making them, no?

    "But if knowledge is a natural phenomenon, there is no reason to expect it to conform to our estimation of its worth."

    Perhaps knowledge isn't *entirely* a natural phenomena, but at least, in part, a social one. Sperber and Mercier's account of reason might be a model here: knowledge, like reason, evolved, BUT it evolved for social purposes. The material processes that constitute knowledge are natural, but the conditions for success or failure of knowledge claims are (at least some times) social. "You don't know it, unless you can show it" to coin a phrase.

    That would fit something like a Jamesian/pragmatist view of knowledge: a belief counts as knowledge only if you can *use* it in some way. A lucky guess wouldn't count as knowledge on this account, until after your guess is confirmed.

    ReplyDelete
  4. Hi Garret, you're right about my Plato example. I don't actually have a problem with ad hominem reasoning in general, though. If you do have good reasons for doubting a person's views- and we certainly do with Plato- then explaining why they hold them by reference to their personal circumstances is the natural next step. Of course it's not ok to hold it dogmatically, and it's often hard to falsify explanations like these.

    I think the notion of success you are using here with reference to Sperber and Mercier is success in actually convincing others. But I don't think S&M would say you don't know something unless you can convince others. Others just won't accept that you know it.

    Similarly with the Jamesian account, I think. It's not that you don't have the knowledge prior to actually putting it to use. We just won't conclude that you do until then.

    ReplyDelete