Recently as I was caring for an elderly relative, I started
to wonder what a good life would look like for her…and other elderly Americans.
The number of Americans aged 65 or older has increased steadily over the last
century with declining fertility and mortality rates and is projected to rise
rapidly in the future. In 1994, one in eight Americans were 65 or older and, by
2050, as many as one
in five Americans could be elderly. Diseases that affect the elderly such
as dementia
or Alzheimer’s also are projected to rise.
It may be convenient for those of us who are younger and
healthier now to assume there is an inverse relationship between our happiness
and our health. The healthier we are the happier we are; the less healthy we
are the less happy we are. We may fatalistically assume with age and illness will
come less happiness.
Of course, our outlook depends on our conception of the good
life. Consistent with some normative theories, happiness consists of a life
lived well and a proper balance of the things that comprise our lives such as health,
knowledge, life projects (e.g., careers), and the arts and entertainment (i.e.,
our hobbies). Maybe it is reasonable to believe that we will be—and even that we
ought to be—less happy as we have less of the things that currently comprise our
happiness. We may even argue for some version of ageism or ableism.
Ageism: we ought to prefer those who are younger.
Ableism: we ought to prefer those who able-bodied.
The problem with ageism and ableism is that certain features
of our lives such as age and health generally are amoral or morally arbitrary.
If we are committed to the view that a person should only be responsible for
features over which she has some significant measure of control, then adopting
a theory of the good life based on features over which a person has little or
no control is morally problematic. In such cases, you may have a theory of
life—a way of looking at life, but not a theory of a good life. A good life is
evaluative of how a person lived given her circumstances, not simply an
evaluation of the circumstances. We generally do not have any significant
measure of control over our age at any given moment or whether we are
able-bodied (although one may intentionally bring about an illness or
disability, but such cases I assume are uncommon).
Moreover, the view that happiness depends on youth and
health does not seem morally preferable. Barring unfortunate circumstances,
we’ll all grow old and die. As part of our universal human condition, it would
be preferable to have a more holistic and healthier approach. A more holistic
and healthier outlook of our aging selves and the elderly in our lives may
involve (1) recognizing that the balance of things that comprise our lives
changes over time and (2) focusing more on life in its entirety rather than at
any given moment.
First, the things that comprise a good life may include our
careers and our hobbies, but as we grow older our priorities and the balance of
these things changes. Rather than focusing on our careers, we may have more time
for the arts and entertainment.
Second, and because for those who are approaching the end of
their lives or those who suffer with disease or disability for whom even the
pursuit of the arts and entertainment may be difficult, it may not be enough
simply to reorganize one’s priorities. What I want to suggest is that greater
happiness awaits us in our old age (or, for those of us who believe in life
after physical death, even after death).
This is consistent with Aristotle’s conception of happiness.
Aristotle wrote: “For this cause also children cannot be happy, for they are
not old enough to be capable of noble acts; when children are spoken of as
happy, it is in compliment to their promise for the future. Happiness, as we
said, requires both complete goodness and a complete lifetime.” (Nicomachean Ethics, bk. 1, ch. 9, see
also bk. 1, ch. 7). It is only at the end of a person’s life that we can know
whether a person has lived well and thereby achieved happiness.1 Happiness
is not a feeling at a given moment but a completed life that has been lived
well.
An elderly person in a nursing home who has lived to the
fullest and who has lived for others is
happy. The person may appreciate and enjoy this fact by reminiscing about the
past, but subjective mental states (memories or a feeling of pleasure) are not necessary
for happiness.2 Even if a person suffers severe intellectual or
physical disabilities and can no longer add to her happiness by actively
exercising virtue, it is still true of the person who has lived well that she is happy. The person may be happy
despite the “reverses and vicissitudes” of fortune.
For persons with severe intellectual and physical disabilities,
the balance mentioned in (1) may look very differently but may still allow for
a life lived well. The holistic approach in (2) requires, as it does in
everyone’s case, a consideration of the person’s circumstances and social
context. A life lived well has less to do with accomplishing great things as
measured in absolute terms and more to do with doing your best with what you’ve
been given. Some people with disabilities—such as Helen Keller—have lived
far better lives by choosing to live well and to live for others than many
fully abled persons.
Please don’t get me wrong; I am not saying that happiness is
unaffected by age or illness. I am saying that we need to have a healthier
outlook toward our aging selves and those who are elderly among us. One way3
to do this is to see (and respect) the elderly for the complete life that they’ve
lived rather than the sick or aging person before us at a given moment.
________________________________
1. See Paul
Farwell, “Aristotle and the Complete Life,” History of Philosophy Quarterly
12(3): 247-263 (1995).
2. Kurt
Pritzl, “Aristotle and Happiness After Death: Nicomachean Ethics 1.10-11,”
Classical Philology 78(2): 101-111 (1983).
3. Another
way is to live by this Christian imperative: “love your aging neighbor, as you
love your aging self.” Frits de Lange, “Loving Later Life: Aging and the Love
Imperative” Journal of the Society of Christian Ethics 33(2): 169-184 (2013).